Lucas Burns
December 10, 2018
Kripke’s Argument is Ad Hominem
In Lecture III of Naming and Necessity, Kripke presents an anti-materialist argument that directly challenges the mind-brain identity theorists’ physicalism. Kripke is not concerned with any other form of physicalism (e.g., view on propositional attitudes) and does not believe that they will be successful in refuting any parts of his argument1. Kripke challenges the identity theorist to explain how a semantic stable necessity (i.e., it refers to the same thing across all possible worlds) can appear contingently true (i.e., for it to simultaneously be true yet possible false) to someone who already believes that it is true. Only an identity theorist would believe that the identity is true, therefore the argument is directed toward the identity theorist’s view. If water is semantically unstable, it would refer to different things depending on how the world turned out to be, but if the reference is fixed as ‘that stuff’, whatever it may be, that is odorless, falls from the sky, and nourishes me, then water is still semantically unstable.
The challenge that Kripke presents is specifically geared toward identity theorists. Only an identity theorist would believe that pain is identical to c-fibers firing, and if this claim is true, it is necessary. The identity statement appears contingent because we can imagine a world in which one exists without the other. If this appearance can be explained away, then the mind-brain identity is possibly false. The appearance of contingency cannot be explained away by identity theorists. Therefore, the identity is not a necessary one and is therefore not true either
Within this exposition, I will argue that Papineau’s interpretation of Kripke’s anti-materialist argument in Naming and Necessity is correct: it is ad hominem to the mind-brain identity theorist. I will first give quotes from Naming and Necessity to prove my point in that it was directed towards an identity theorist. Second, I will explain how the appearance of contingency arises through necessary a posteriori truths. Finally, I will explain how physicalists can respond to Kripke’s argument.
Kripke presented his argument to the identity theorists very explicitly and repetitively. Identity theorists are called out for the one’s specifically believing some identity, such as c-fiber stimulation and pain. Here are four quotes calling out the identity theorist specifically:
Kripke believes that theoretical identities generally involve two rigid designators and are what science aims to discover, making them necessary a posteriori10. One of his main objectives is to show that theoretical identity sentences are necessary, if true (e.g., water is H2O). Theoretical notions in science are fixed by descriptions because they hold some relationship with the device that is measuring it, as well as the humans observing it.
Brain states can be imagined sympathetically or perceptually. To imagine what you yourself feel like whenever that brain state is present (e.g., c-fibers firing) is to sympathetically imagine the brain state. To perceptually imagine a brain state is what it is like to observe this brain state from an outside perspective (e.g., an fMRI scan). The two ways of imagining a brain state mean that the identity between pain and c-fiber stimulation is a posteriori because one could observe an fMRI scan of a brain and know that it is the result of c-fiber stimulation, as well as feel the sensation of pain—but not know that the fMRI scan and their sensation of pain are the same exact thing. This would be a lack of knowledge on the individual’s part, and once they gain empirical evidence that it was the case, they would no longer think that they were different. Although, it is still possible for an individual to imagine a possible world in which pain is present without the stimulation of c-fibers or vice versa. This conceptualization would not grant an appearance of contingency to the person who just became aware that they were the same thing, because there is no reason for them to believe that pain’s being identical to the stimulation of c-fibers could have turned out any other way.
Mind-brain assertions of identity lack a contingent reference-fixer and do not choose their referents indirectly through definite or cluster descriptions. Moreover, if one were to conceive of a world in which c-fibers firing doesn’t appear sympathetically (i.e., you yourself experiencing pain or another), the person is not stipulating the fact that c-fiber stimulation (i.e., pain) might not have some feature that is contingent that it is actually displaying—instead, they are supposing that c-fiber firings might be present without pain. By doing this does not explain how physicalists can think that c-fiber stimulation and pain could separate, since it presupposes that the pain and c-fiber stimulation are two distinct states—separate from one another—which is contrary to their outlook. Once the belief that pain is identical to c-fiber stimulation is acquired, there is no room for any further thought that some pain-seeming or pain-appearing state might not be the stimulation of c-fibers. All this would be is the the thought that pains might not be the c-fibers firing—which is the belief that the identity theorist rules out.
Kripke’s anti-materialist argument is presented in a way that allows mind-brain identities to appear as if they can be separated. Identity theorists will say that these identities should not appear in a way they could be possibly separated; but they do appear in such a way; therefore, physicalism is false. This arguments conclusion does is lead a physicalist to the metaphysical conclusion that mind-body do not stand in an identical relation—instead, it supports the idea that it is not intuitive to believe mind-brain identities.
Physicalists are left with a possibility of explaining the consistent appearance of possible falsity (i.e., contingency) by explaining on some level that they do not fully believe the mind-brain identities posited, or any for that matter. And this is why they appear possibly false. Physicalists will still be able to hold on to their belief at a theoretical level, such as the evidence for a range of claims like pains and c-fiber stimulation is sufficient for belief. Physicalists can also allow that this evidence does not give them an intuitive edge to the identities, and that persistent appearance of possible falsity is merely arising from their intuitive feeling that these beliefs they hold are actually false.
Sources Consulted
Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and Necessity. Harvard University Press. pp. 134-155
Papineau, D. (2007). Kripke’s Proof is Ad Hominem and Not Two-Dimensional. pp. 475-494
Papineau, D. (2007). Kripke’s Proof that We are All Intuitive Dualists.
1 Naming and Necessity, p. 150
2 Naming and Necessity, p. 146
3 Naming and Necessity, p. 149
4 Naming and Necessity, p. 150
5 Naming and Necessity, p. 155
6 Naming and Necessity, p. 134
7 Kripke’s Proof is Ad Hominem Not Two-Dimensional, p. 476
8 Naming and Necessity, p. 147-48.
9 Kripke’s Proof is Ad Hominem Not Two-Dimensional, p. 476
10 Naming and Necessity p. 140
11 Naming and Necessity, p. 148
12 Kripke’s Proof is that We are All Intuitive Dualists, no pp.
13 Kripke’s Proof is that We are All Intuitive Dualists, no pp.
14 Kripke’s Proof is that We are All Intuitive Dualists, no pp.
15 Kripke’s Proof is that We are All Intuitive Dualists, no pp.